Syllabus | Opinion [ Kennedy ] | Concurrence [ Stevens ] | Concurrence [ Scalia ] | Dissent [ OConnor ] | Dissent [ Souter ] | Dissent [ Breyer ] |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
HTML version PDF version | HTML version PDF version | HTML version PDF version | HTML version PDF version | HTML version PDF version | HTML version PDF version | HTML version PDF version |
Scalia, J., concurring
CITY OF BOERNE, PETITIONER v. P. F. FLORES, ARCHBISHOP OF SAN ANTONIO, AND
UNITED STATES
ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FIFTH CIRCUIT
[June 25, 1997]
Justice Scalia, with whom Justice Stevens joins, concurring.
I write to respond briefly to the claim of Justice OConnors dissent (hereinafter the dissent) that historical materials support a result contrary to the one reached in Employment Div., Dept. of Human Resources of Ore. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990). See post, p. ___ (dissenting opinion). We held in Smith that the Constitutions Free Exercise Clause does not relieve an individual of the obligation to comply with a valid and neutral law of general applicability on the ground that the law proscribes (or prescribes) conduct that his religion prescribes (or proscribes).
The dissent first claims that Smiths interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause departs from the understanding reflected in various statutory and constitutional protections of religion enacted by Colonies, States, and Territories in the period leading up to the ratification of the Bill of Rights. Post, at 814. But the protections afforded by those enactments are in fact more consistent with Smiths interpretation of free exercise than with the dissents understanding of it. The Free Exercise Clause, the dissent claims, is best understood as an affirmative guarantee of the right to participate in religious practices and conduct without impermissible governmental interference, even when such conduct conflicts with a neutral, generally applicable law; thus, even neutral laws of general application may be invalid if they burden religiously motivated conduct. Post, at 3. However, the early free exercise enactments cited by the dissent protect only against action that is taken for or in respect of religion, post, at 811 (Maryland Act Concerning Religion of 1649, Rhode Island Charter of 1663, and New Hampshire Constitution); or action taken on account of religion, post, at 1112 (Maryland Declaration of Rights of 1776 and Northwest Ordinance of 1787); or discriminat[ory] action, post, at 10 (New York Constitution); or, finally (and unhelpfully for purposes of interpreting free exercise in the Federal Constitution), action that interferes with the free exercise of religion, post, at 8, 11 (Maryland Act Concerning Religion of 1649 and Georgia Constitution). It is eminently arguable that application of neutral, generally applicable laws of the sort the dissent refers tosuch as zoning laws, post, at 4would not constitute action taken for, in respect of, or on account of ones religion, or discriminatory action.
Assuming, however, that the affirmative protection of religion accorded by the early free exercise enactments sweeps as broadly as the dissents theory would require, those enactments do not support the dissents view, since they contain provisos that significantly qualify the affirmative protection they grant. According to the dissent, the provisos support its view because they would have been superfluous if the Court was correct in Smith that generally applicable laws are enforceable regardless of religious conscience. Post, at 12. I disagree. In fact, the most plausible reading of the free exercise enactments
(if their affirmative provisions are read broadly, as the dissents view requires) is a virtual restatement of Smith: Religious exercise shall be permitted so long as it does not violate general laws governing conduct. The provisos in the enactments negate a license to act in a manner unfaithfull to the Lord Proprietary (Maryland Act Concerning Religion of 1649), or behav[e] in other than a peaceabl[e] and quie[t] manner (Rhode Island Charter
of 1663), or disturb the public peace (New Hampshire Constitution), or interfere with the peace [and] safety of th[e] State (New York, Maryland, and Georgia Constitutions), or demea[n] oneself in other than a peaceable and orderly manner (Northwest Ordinance of 1787). See post, at 812. At the time these provisos were enacted, keeping peace and order seems to have meant, precisely, obeying the laws. [E]very breach of law is against the peace. Queen v. Lane, 6 Mod. 128, 87 Eng. Rep. 884, 885 (Q. B. 1704). Even as late as 1828, when Noah
Webster published his American Dictionary of the English Language, he gave as one of the meanings of peace: 8. Public tranquility; that quiet, order and security which is guaranteed by the laws; as, to keep the peace; to break
the peace. 2 An American Dictionary of the English Language 31 (1828).1 This limitation upon the scope of religious exercise would have been in accord with the background political philosophy of the age (associated most prominently with John Locke), which regarded freedom as the right to do only what was not lawfully prohibited, West, The Case Against a Right to Religion-Based Exemptions, 4 Notre Dame J. of Law, Ethics & Public Policy 591, 624 (1990). Thus, the disturb-the-peace caveats apparently permitted government to deny religious freedom, not merely in the event of violence or force, but, more generally, upon the occurrence of illegal actions. Hamburger, supra, at 918919.2 And while, under this interpretation, these early free exercise enactments support the Courts judgment in Smith, I see no sensible interpretation that could cause them to support what I understand to be the position of Justice OConnor, or any of Smiths other critics. No one in that camp, to my knowledge, contends that their favored compelling state interest test conforms to any possible interpretation of breach of peace and orderi.e., that only violence or force, or any other category of action (more limited than violation of law) which can possibly be conveyed by the phrase peace and order, justifies state prohibition of religiously motivated conduct.
Apart from the early free exercise enactments of Colonies, States, and Territories, the dissent calls attention to those bodies, and the Continental Congresss, legislative accommodation of religious practices prior to ratification of the Bill of Rights. Post, at 1417. This accommodationwhich took place both before and after enactment of the state constitutional protections of religious libertysuggests (according to the dissent) that the drafters and ratifiers of the First Amendment assumed courts would apply the Free Exercise Clause similarly. Post, at 17. But that legislatures sometimes (though not always)3 found it appropriate, ibid., to accommodate religious practices does not establish that accommodation was understood to be constitutionally mandated by the Free Exercise Clause. As we explained in Smith, [T]o say that a nondiscriminatory religious-practice exemption is permitted, or even that it is desirable, is not to say that it is constitutionally required. 494 U.S., at 890. Values that are protected against government interference through enshrinement in the Bill of Rights are not thereby banished from the political process. Ibid.
The dissents final source of claimed historical support consists of statements of certain of the Framers in the context of debates about proposed legislative enactments or debates over general principles (not in connection with the drafting of State or Federal Constitutions). Those statements are subject to the same objection as was the evidence about legislative accommodation: There is no reason to think they were meant to describe what was constitutionally required (and judicially enforceable), as opposed to what was thought to be legislatively or even morally desirable. Thus, for example, the pamphlet written by James Madison opposing Virginias proposed general assessment for support of religion, post, at 1719, does not argue that the assessment would violate the
free exercise provision in the Virginia Declaration of Rights, although that provision had been enacted into
law only eight years earlier, post, at 14; rather the pamphlet argues that the assessment wrongly placed civil society ahead of personal religious belief and, thus, should not be approved by the legislators, post, at 18. Likewise, the letter from George Washington to the Quakers, post, at 20, by its own terms refers to Washingtons wish and desire that religion be accommodated, not his belief
that existing constitutional provisions required accommodation. These and other examples offered by the dissent reflect the speakers views of the proper relationship between government and religion, post, at 21, but not
their views (at least insofar as the content or context of the material suggests) of the constitutionally required relationship. The one exception is the statement by
Thomas Jefferson that he considered the government
of the United States as interdicted by the Constitution from intermeddling with religious institutions, their doctrines, discipline, or exercises, post, at 1920 (internal quotation marks omitted); but it is quite clear that Jefferson did not in fact espouse the broad principle of affirmative accommodation advocated by the dissent, see McConnell, 103 Harv. L. Rev., at 14491452.
It seems to me that the most telling point made by the dissent is to be found, not in what it says, but in what it fails to say. Had the understanding in the period surrounding the ratification of the Bill of Rights been that the various forms of accommodation discussed by the dissent were constitutionally required (either by State Constitutions or by the Federal Constitution), it would be surprising not to find a single state or federal case refusing to enforce a generally applicable statute because of its failure to make accommodation. Yet the dissent cites noneand to my knowledge, and to the knowledge of the academic defenders of the dissents position, see, e.g., id., at 1504, 15061511 (discussing early cases), none exists. The closest one can come in the period prior to 1850 is the decision of a New York City municipal court in 1813, holding that the New York Constitution of 1777, quoted post, at 10, required acknowledgement of a priest-penitent privilege, to protect a Catholic priest from being compelled to testify as to the contents of a confession. People v. Philips, Court of General Sessions, City of New York (June 14, 1813), excerpted in Privileged Communications to Clergymen, 1 Cath. Lawyer 199 (1955). Even this lone case is weak authority, not only because it comes from a minor court,4 but also because it did not involve a statute, and the same result might possibly have been achieved (without invoking constitutional entitlement) by the courts simply modifying the common-law rules of evidence to recognize such a privilege. On the other side of the ledger, moreover, there are two cases, from the Supreme Court of Pennsylvania, flatly rejecting the dissents view. In Simons Executors v. Gratz, 2 Pen. & W. 412 (Pa. 1831), the court held that
a litigant was not entitled to a continuance of trial on the ground that appearing on his Sabbath would violate his religious principles. And in Stansbury v. Marks, 2 Dall. 213 (Pa. 1793), decided just two years after the ratification of the Bill of Rights, the court imposed a fine on a witness who refused to be sworn, because it was his Sabbath.5
I have limited this response to the new items of historical evidence brought forward by todays dissent. (The dissents claim that [b]efore Smith, our free exercise cases were generally in keeping with the dissents view, post, at 3, is adequately answered in Smith itself.) The historical evidence marshalled by the dissent cannot fairly be said to demonstrate the correctness of Smith; but it
is more supportive of that conclusion than destructive
of it. And, to return to a point I made earlier, that evidence is not compatible with any theory I am familiar
with that has been proposed as an alternative to Smith. The dissents approach has, of course, great popular attraction. Who can possibly be against the abstract proposition that government should not, even in its general, nondiscriminatory laws, place unreasonable burdens upon religious practice? Unfortunately, however, that abstract proposition must ultimately be reduced to concrete cases. The issue presented by Smith is, quite simply, whether the people, through their elected representatives, or rather this Court, shall control the outcome of those concrete cases. For example, shall it be the determination of
this Court, or rather of the people, whether (as the dis-
sent apparently believes, post,, at 4) church construc-
tion will be exempt from zoning laws? The historical evidence put forward by the dissent does nothing to undermine the conclusion we reached in Smith: It shall be the people.
Notes
1. The word licentious, used in several of the early enactments, likewise meant [e]xceeding the limits of law. 2 An American Dictionary of the English Language 6 (1828).
2. The same explanation applies, of course, to George Masons initial draft of Virginias religious liberty clause, see post, at 1213. When it said unless, under colour of religion, any man disturb the peace of society, it probably meant unless under color of religion any man break the law. Thus, it is not the case that both Masons and [James] Madisons formulations envisioned that, where there was a conflict [between religious exercise and generally applicable laws], a persons interest in freely practicing his religion was to be balanced against state interests, post, at 14at least insofar as regulation of conduct was concerned.
3. The dissent mentions, for example, that only seven of the thirteen Colonies had exempted Quakers from military service by the mid-1700s; and that virtually all of the States had enacted oath exemptions by 1789. Post, at 1516 (emphasis added).
4. The Court of General Sessions was a mayors court, and the ruling in Phillips was made by DeWitt Clinton, the last mayor to preside over that court, which was subsequently reconstituted as the Court of Common Pleas. Clinton had never been a jurist, and indeed had never practiced law. Some years before Phillips, he was instrumental in removing the political disabilities of Catholics in New York. See 4 Dictionary of American Biography 221222, 224 (1943).
5. Indeed, the author of Simons Executors could well have written Smith: [C]onsiderations of policy address themselves with propriety to the legislature, and not to a magistrate whose course is prescribed not by discretion, but rules already established. 2 Pen. & W., at 417.